Scotland’s legal landscape was, at the time, going through perhaps even more dramatic
changes than England, and Kames was a strong advocate for a judicial, rather than
legislative, route to support that change: “The legal writings of the Scottish judge and
philosopher, Henry Home, Lord Kames, contain, amongst much else, one of the
eighteenth century's most ambitious and articulate programs of judicial law reform.
Kames's elaborate defense of the judicial route to legal improvement, as well as his more
general approach to legal theory, owed much to the specifically Scottish setting in which
he trained and professionally served, and no account of his career and corpus could
afford to neglect this Scottish context” (Lieberman 1989, 144).
Like Smith, Kames looked at the world from a broad frame of reference. By 1781, “he
had assembled a massive, if rather prolix, corpus of over twenty volumes that could serve
as an index to nearly all of the intellectual pursuits of the Scottish Enlightenment,
encompassing such topics as morals, religion, law, government, natural philosophy,
political economy, education, aesthetics, and of course history” (Lieberman 1989, 146).
It is also clear that Smith and Kames strongly influenced each other in their thinking
and their views. Lieberman tells us that Kames “… effectively promoted the academic
fortunes of Adam Smith …” and Adam Smith in turn observed that “we must every one of
us acknowledge Kames for our master ….” (Lieberman 1989, 146) In fact, Kames was
patron not just to Adam Smith, but also to a number of the other most influential thinkers
of the time, including David Hume and John Millar.
Kames is credited for having described the ‘four-stage’ advancement of society, from
hunter-gatherer to herder, then agricultural and finally commercial society. This model
was fundamental to the legal debate that was going on at the time. (It is just as important
to the debate that is now taking place, as we move into a fifth stage, a technology driven
society where we must reassess our relationship with social platforms and complex AI-
driven, semi-autonomous systems). In the first two stages, no laws were considered
necessary save for those issued by the family, clan or tribe head. The agricultural stage
introduced new occupations and made the work of those individuals valuable to others,
requiring the law to develop principles to guide these new relationships. The age of
commerce (and, for the English, empire) created even more complex societal relations,
requiring significant developments in the law to support these changes. Kames, like
Mansfield, dismissed legislation as incapable of resolving these challenges and believed
that the only effective solution lay in the development of the common law.
While “Kames presented one of the first published versions of the "four stages" theory
of societal development … Meek argued that … he probably learned the theory from
Smith's lectures on jurisprudence” (Lieberman 1989, 149, fn 25, Meek 1976, 102-7).
Indeed, the links between Kames and Smith went much further than this and their views
on law and jurisprudence were at the centre of their thinking: “As in the case of other
contemporary Scottish philosophers, jurisprudence provided the disciplinary context and
much of the structure for Kames's explorations in social theory. It was in his essays on
law that he first revealed many of the same general sociological interests displayed by
Adam Smith in his Lectures on Jurisprudence or by John Millar in The Origin of the
Distinction of Ranks. The distinctive concern of this body of eighteenth-century legal
speculation, according to the testimony of John Millar in his An Historical View of